Chapter Three
REPRESENTATIONALISM VERSUS
DIRECT REALISM
* * *
3.1 What representationalism is
3.2 Arguments for representationalism
3.3 That contemporary foundationalists are
representationalists
3.4 That representationalism fails
3.5 Defeating the skeptic quickly
3.6 Illusions, relativity, and direct realism
* * *
3.1
What representationalism is
Contemporary
foundationalists share a cluster of fundamental beliefs about the nature of
perception, about the initial legitimacy of the challenge of skepticism, about
the connection between doing epistemology and doing metaphysics, and,
accordingly, about how a defense of foundationalism should proceed. They differ over many of the details, of
course, yet a broad agreement on these several philosophically basic issues
characterizes the approach of the major
20th century foundationalists. That
broad area of agreement is representationalism.
Representationalism's
distinctive epistemological thesis is that knowledge or justified belief about
external objects is indirectly arrived at.
Such knowledge is based on prior knowledge about phenomenal states. The prior knowledge about one's phenomenal
states is held to be justified non-inferentially, i.e., it doesn't depend upon
other beliefs. External reality sets
the standards for truth — i.e., truth is
still defined in terms of correspondence — but the justification of belief proceeds entirely from the
"inside," i.e., subjectively and without reference to external
reality.
Idealists attack the notion that one can derive knowledge about external
objects from knowledge about phenomenal states. Let's call this the "You can't get there from here"
position. If this is right, and if perception
at best yields phenomenal knowledge, then one is stuck "inside";
one's knowledge, including one's standards for justification and truth, become entirely dependent upon the
subject. Typically, versions of the
coherence model are then advocated for both justification and truth.
Direct realists agree with the idealist "you can't get there from
here" charge against the representationalists. But they deny the representationalist claim that one's knowledge
of external objects is based upon prior knowledge of phenomenal states. In fact, they typically reverse the order of
dependence: knowledge of phenomenal states, being self-reflective, presupposes
knowledge of external fact.[1] One begins directly in contact with reality
and builds from there. Reality provides
one's standards for both justification and truth.
The claims of this chapter are that all of the major contemporary versions of
foundationalism are representationalist in principle, that representationalism
fails, that the major arguments against foundationalism attack only (with one
exception) representationalist foundationalism, and that the problems that
typically motivate representationalism can be solved without resort to
representationalism. If this analysis
is correct, then it follows that a foundationalism based upon direct realism is
still an option, whether or not the arguments often advanced against
representationalist foundationalism are sound.
3.2
Arguments for representationalism
Historically, representationalism arises in the context of wondering how best
to deal with two epistemological problems — skepticism, and perceptual
relativity and illusions.
Skepticism challenges claims to knowledge or justified belief in a number of
forms. The most powerful (and hence
most widely used) skeptical challenge comes in the form of a question directed
toward any claim to justifed belief or knowledge: "How do you know you're
not X right now?" — where any
of the following can be substituted for the X: dreaming, subject to a malicious demon's pranks, a brain in a
vat. Not being able to answer the question
leads one to hedge one's claims and to search for a source of certainty immune
to the skeptic's question. Representationalism
has been seen as providing such a haven, as we shall investigate below.
Representationalist accounts of perception and accompanying
representationalist accounts of justification have also been the normal
response to illusions and relativity.
One's account of perception is obviously central to an account of
foundationalism, since perception is, if anything is, the locus of our most
fundamental commerce with reality.
Therefore, facts about perception that are problematic, e.g., illusions
and relativity, are special concerns for foundationalism. To see how such accounts directly affect
the question of foundationalism, let us review the progression.
Take a standard case of perceptual relativity, say, a coin that appears
elliptical in varying degrees as one views it while moving around it. We know that the coin does not vary, yet
something about our experience of it does.
We have two facts, then, to analyze and integrate:
(1) The real object (the coin) does not vary.
(2) Something about the awareness does vary.
We have two
options at this point. We could say
that the object of awareness changes, in which case it follows that the object
of awareness is not the real object. Or
we could say that the awareness changes.
The most common answer, until recently, has been the former, which is the
standard representationalist line.
Representationalists will introduce intermediary objects of perception
and hold that the perceiver is aware of the intermediary objects only — at
least that is all the perceiver is aware of directly;
the perceiver can be said to be aware of the real, external object indirectly,
by means of an inference. Let us use
the term "sense data" to stand for all of the candidates
representationalists offer as intermediary objects between the perceiver and
the object.
(The argument from illusion generates the same conclusion as the argument from
relativity via the same form of argument: the real railroad tracks are
straight; my awareness does not show what I am aware of to be straight;
therefore, what I am aware of cannot be the real railroad tracks.[2])
But before the representationalist conclusion follows, the other alternative —
that what changes is the awareness — must be eliminated as an option. Perceptual representationalists accomplish
this, often implicitly, by denying that awareness could change. Awareness, on this view, is pure: it has no
features of its own. It is simply pure
inspection, it is a "mirror of nature," it is "diaphanous."[3] So there is no way it could vary, which
means it must be the same in any instance.
Then the needed conclusion follows: any variation can only be in the object
of awareness.
The reason behind this diaphanous/mirror of nature view seems to be this: if
one's awareness had its own identity, which would be partly responsible for the
variations in perceptions, then its own identity would distort the resulting
awareness, and then it could not know its object. The point is clear in Aristotle: nous
cannot have any form of its own, for this would interfere with or distort its
reception of the forms of its objects.[4]
The claim can be separated from Aristotle's form-impression account, leaving it
in the following form: if awareness is to be a cognitive phenomenon, it must
both take an object and not contribute anything to the awareness — which means
it must be pure inspection. And if it
is pure inspection, the changing qualities of perception cannot be ascribed to
it.[5]
The point is also clear in Aquinas when he contrasts the perfect knowledge of
intellectual substances with ours: the intellectual substances, "knowing
something external to themselves, in a certain sense they go outside of themselves."[6] Aquinas is here indicating the implicit
standard: to have perfect awareness of something external, there must be no
intermediary organ to distort the resulting awareness; perfect awareness is a
pure merging of subject and object. We
humans of course cannot effect this pure merging; we have no way to jump
outside our heads, so to speak, in order to attain the perfect grasp. The next best thing, then, is for our medium
of awareness to be diaphanous, i.e., to have no distorting identity of its
own.
This diaphanous standard is also a dominant theme in Eastern philosophy: one
must seek to merge oneself with reality; one should become one with the
universe in the sense that one should erase all distinctions between subject
and object, because the subjective equals the illusory and unreal, and if the
subject retains any individual identity then true reality is unattainable.
What is at work here is a fundamental unease over the distinction between
object and subject. In its purest form,
as in much of Eastern philosophy, this unease manifests itself in a desire to
erase the subject. The underlying
premise seems to be that if there is any difference between the knowing subject
and the object, then the one cannot be said to know the other. In other words, subject and object must
literally be identical. Let's call this
the Identity Thesis.
While Aristotle and Aquinas do not accept the extreme version of the Identity
Thesis, they do accept the view that awareness must be a diaphanous phenomenon;
this is to enable a partial identity of subject and object while at the same
time preserving a distinction between the two.
Representationalists since Locke and Descartes have delimited the scope of the
diaphanous portion of our faculties.
It is clear that our sense organs themselves are not mere diaphanous
directions upon an object. They are
physical organs; they have definite identities of their own. But if the diaphanous standard is correct,
then it must follow that our sense organs do not put us directly in contact
with reality as it really is. The pure
inspection must come at a later stage, after the work of the senses is done,
which means one's diaphanous awareness inspects what one's non-diaphanous
senses present it.
We have now the fundamental ingredients of the representationalist model of
perception. The only way to combine
the three premises — that the real object does not change, that one's
diaphanous awareness does not change, and that the senses are not diaphanous
modes of awareness — is to hold that the senses present one with intermediary
objects of awareness. This is the
representationalist conclusion.
We start, then, with awareness of intermediary sense data. But there is an added benefit to this
conclusion: since one's diaphanous awareness is simply pure inspection of sense
data, propositions about one's sense data would seem to be incorrigible. There is at this point no distoring medium
between awareness and the object of awareness.
Hence one also has in propositions about sense data a source of
certainty immune to skeptical objections.
Thus the introduction of sense data also satisfies the second of our
desiderata. This is certainly
attractive to many foundationalists.
The next stage is to infer the existence of external objects: it
follows, therefore, that foundationalists who accept this account of
perception thus follow the standard pattern of attempting to show how one can
derive justified beliefs about external objects indirectly via incorrigible
beliefs about sense data. Hence
representationalist theories of perception generate representationalist
theories of justification. Only such
representationalist accounts, it is felt, can meet the demands of answering
the skeptic and accounting for perceptual illusions and relativity.
Yet the posited intermediary sense data have been found to be extremely
problematic objects. Are they mental or
physical? Do they have backsides? The documented difficulties in answering
these and related questions have led many to reject the sense data analysis,
including Chisholm and Moser.[7] But in rejecting sense data we are thrust
back into the problem of integrating the two facts about perception:
(1) The real object (the coin) does not vary.
(2) Something about the awareness does vary.
If we reject intermediary sense data, then we must opt for the only
alternative: what varies is the awareness.
Awareness is thus not an unchanging
direction upon an object. The solution
must be to understand the sensuous qualities of perception as modifying the
awareness and not the object of awareness, if indeed one exists. Awareness is an action, and since adverbs
are what modify descriptions of actions, acts of sensing should be described
adverbially.
So far the adverbialist option is not necessarily representationalist. One still could hold that acts of sensing
are intentional and take real things as their objects, or, more generally, that
acts of awareness are necessarily intentional in the strong sense: that the
intentional relation is a real relation.
One could argue that the object of perception doesn't change in the case
of the elliptical coin but that only the manner or form in which it is
perceived changes. The adverbial
description of the awareness would then be integrated with an account of its
relation to its object. This would
amount to a direct realist position — which is the position I think is right
and which will be explored further below.
Some adverbialists (e.g., Chisholm and Moser), however, drop the real
intentional relation and hold that the act of awareness has no necessary
direction upon an object. At least two
additional considerations motivate this.
One is a desire not to make ontological commitments where unnecessary in
doing one's epistemology.[8] A second is hallucinations: hallucinations
seem to be an experiential phenomenon in which no real object exists
corresponding to the experience. In the
case of hallucinations, it cannot be that a real object is being distorted or
relativised, as is possible to claim in the case of illusions and relativity;
the hallucinatory experience seems to be created ex
nihilo. Add to this the standard
skeptical conjectures about brains-in-a-vat, and the conclusion seems to be
that awareness could, in certain cases, occur entirely without an object.[9] We have no automatic method of telling
whether a given awareness is a perception or a hallucination, so in the
interests of having a unified theory of experience, of which perception and hallucination
are two species, the non-intentional nature of hallucinations is decisive. What is crucial is the manner and character
of the experience; what is contingent is the external relation. These two considerations dictate that, given
the failure of the sense data theories, acts of sensing are to be described
non-relationally as self-contained phenomena; and if an act of sensing is in
fact related to a real object, then this is a contingent fact that is external
to the act of sensing, and one that must be analyzed separately.
The important point for foundationalism is that by dropping the necessary
relation between acts of awareness and real objects one makes indirect and thus
more difficult the process by which one arrives at justified propositions about
external reality. The nonrelational
adverbial account is still in principle compatible with a direct realist
account of perception, but it does require a representationalist account of
justified belief. A further price to be
paid is that by dropping the real intentional character of experience, it is
hard to see how experience can be a cognitive phenomenon. In addition, it becomes that much harder to
see how a hierarchy of propositions (which are cognitive) can be justified by
something that is not cognitive, i.e., experience.[10]
Let us conclude this section with a summary statement of the progression of
this representationalist argument.
1. If perception is a cognitive phenomenon,
then it takes an object.
2. But in the case of perceptual illusions and
relativity, what one is aware of can't be the real object.
3. But perception is cognitive, so it must take
an object.
4. Hence, there must be sense data.
5. Sense data are unacceptable.
6. Therefore, we must drop the taking-an-object
requirement for perception.
7. Hence, it cannot be that perception
necessarily takes an object.
8. Hence, we must formulate perceptual
experiences adverbially and
nonrelationally.
9. Thus, from 1 and 7, perception is not a
cognitive phenomenon.
10. It also follows from 7 that establishing
percept/external object relations require an inference.
3.3
That contemporary foundationalists are representationalists
This representationalist pattern is clearly at work in the writings of Lewis
and Chisholm. Lewis is explicitly
committed to phenomenalism. While
Chisholm is not a phenomenalist, he follows Lewis in making incorrigibility a
requirement for foundational propositions.
Both therefore feel constrained to limit their subject matter to psychological
experiential data; since propositions about such data assert no necessary
connection to anything beyond the data, they can be validated in a manner that
"is absolutely decisive and theoretically complete."[11]
The same procedure is followed in Moser's early writings. There, nonpropositional events of immediate
apprehension are said to justify subjective propositions solely about
phenomenal content; these subjective beliefs in turn justify physical-object
beliefs.[12] The best-explanation model is then pressed
into service in answer to questions about how one gets from subjective to
physical-object propositions.
A modified version of this representationalist procedure is adopted in Moser's
more recent writings. The immediate
data that give rise to propositions are taken nonrelationally, as subjective,
psychological contents: "[s]uch contents do not entail the existence of
anything independent of the perceiver's experience of them."[13] As skeptics have pointed out, any given
experience could be, from the subject's standpoint, any number of things other
than an awareness of an external object.[14] So realism with regard to physical objects
is taken initially as a hypothesis to be
evaluated relative to others. And so
one needs to proceed indirectly in arriving at a justified external-world
proposition.[15]
It is also clear that representationalism is taken as characterizing
contemporary foundationalism by its opponents. Rorty has argued that foundationalism is a delusion peculiar to
post-Cartesian philosophy. Note the
epistemological direction that Rorty is accusing Descartes of having sent
modern philosophy upon: representationalism.[16] Michael Williams, another opponent of
foundationalism, has made the claim that in rejecting foundationalism one is in
effect defending direct realism.[17] Clearly Williams is assuming that
foundationalism is committed to phenomenalism, which is a key
representationalist thesis. In attacking
foundationalism, Sellars also proceeds by noting the representationalist model
that Descartes, Locke, and Kant introduced.
According to this model, our cognitive access to the world is indirect:
we don't have direct access to the facts themselves, but we do have direct,
diaphanous access to the representational states themselves.[18]
As for foundationalism, Sellars sees
whether some form of this representationalist model is workable as "a
central theme" regarding the tenability of foundationalism.[19] Once again, foundationalism and a
representationalist methodology are seen as necessarily linked.
There is certainly some historical justification for seeing the two as
necessarily linked. And so there is
also some justification for inferring that if representationalism fails,
foundationalism also fails. This is
exactly the pattern of argument that antifoundationalists follow. But if foundationalism can be separated from
representationalism, then from representationalism's failure antifoundationalist
conclusions will not follow. In the
next section I argue that representationalism does fail; here I am largely in
agreement with the antifoundationalists and the idealist arguments that they
have traditionally brought to bear against foundationalism.
3.4
That representationalism fails
Representationalism is adopted to allow a foundationalist methodology to
proceed without begging questions against skeptical worries, whether those
worries be about perceptual illusions or evil demons. Representationalism is claimed to allow the foundationalist to proceed
"neutrally," that is, without making any ontological commitments
about the status of perception or about the general relationship between
consciousness and reality.[20] Yet it is held that representationalism can
be adopted without falling into idealism; that is, representationalists hold
that it is possible to generate justified external-world propositions from
nonrelational, subjective starting points.
The purpose of this section is to show that representationalism fails
on both counts: it does not proceed neutrally (i.e., without making ontological
commitments) in response to skepticism, and justified external-world
propositions in principle cannot be generated either from subjective propositions
or experiential states taken as nonrelational subjective states.
Let us first examine the claim that representationalism, at least in the form
in which it appears in the writings of Chisholm and Moser, is ontologically
neutral. Older versions of
representationalism cannot make a claim of neutrality, for at a minimum they
are committed to the existence of sense data, which are posited as a new ontological
category. But, as we have seen,
Chisholm and Moser have made it clear that their use of adverbial appearance
formulations is not to be taken as involving ontological claims. The skeptic is right, they believe: the mere
having of an experience does not imply the existence of an object corresponding
to it; so the experience should be taken nonrelationally.
But there is a problem here. In
avoiding one type of ontological commitment, namely a commitment to external
objects corresponding to experiential states, representationalists have made
another type of commitment, namely to a certain model of mind. Skeptical considerations all depend upon
holding that given experiential states could occur just as they do in the
absence of an external object.
Generalizing this claim, the skeptical premise is that the entire
contents of one's consciousness could be generated just as they are experienced
even if there were no external reality.[21]
This is the skeptical position
Descartes arrives at in the First Meditation.
But this premise presupposes a commitment to the view that consciousness
is not in any fundamental way dependent upon reality for its contents. And that is to say that consciousness
generally is a nonrelational phenomenon.
This is the fundamental source of the view that the relationship between
consciousness and reality has to be argued for. But this is hardly a neutral position ontologically. This is to deny what realists take as an
axiom — that to be conscious is to be conscious of something, that
consciousness cannot create its own contents, that consciousness is a
relational phenomenon. The denial of
realism is not a position neutral with respect to some third alternative. Consciousness is either essentially
relational or it isn't; either position involves a basic ontological
commitment. And if one argues that
relations between conscious states and external realities are not essential to
the conscious state, that instead they are contingent relations to be
established separately, then one has made one's commitment. This is the position Chisholm and Moser
accept.
If representationalism is not an
ontologically neutral response to skepticism, then what of its other thesis,
namely that it is possible to bridge the epistemic gap between nonrelational
subjective states and propositions about external objects?
One is almost tempted to argue that such inferences attempt to derive an
"is" from an "ought".[22]
Once we accept the idea of a strict
epistemological order, we cannot explain how a warranted inference to the
existence of the physical world is possible.[23] Now it is a familiar but forceful idealist
objection to the correspondence theory of truth that if the theory were correct
we could never know whether any of our beliefs were true, since we have no
perspective outside our system of beliefs from which to see that they do not
correspond.[24]
The problem here
is not a new one. On representationalist
grounds, one has access only to one's immediate experiential states. Propositions about such experiential states
include no terms relating the experiential state to an external reality. So how can a proposition that makes
reference to an external reality acquire justification?
Deduction from the subjective propositions will not work. In a valid deduction one cannot have in the
conclusion terms that are not in the premises.[25] Subjective propositions do not contain terms
referring to an external world. The
only way to preserve a deductive structure would be to attempt the rationalist
move of positing innate or a priori
principles that do contain an external-world term in them. But there are two well-known and insurmountable
difficulties inherent in any such project.
First, one would have to justify the claim that such principles could be
innate or a priori. Second, supposing that one had overcome the
first difficulty, one would have the further enormous difficulty of showing
that the innate or a priori principles have
anything to do with the reality they are allegedly about.
An enumerative induction will not work, either. All that follows from such a pattern of reasoning is a proposition
of the form, "All cases of being appeared to X-ly are cases of being appeared to Y-ly."
For these reasons representationalists adopt the best-explanation or
hypothetical induction model, popularized by Russell during his
representationalist phase. As we have
seen, Chisholm and Moser agree that this is the most promising approach. Chisholm argues that we have to beg the
question against the skeptic anyway, and since the external world propositions
square best with our pre-analytic intuitions, they are usually the best
explanation. Moser argues that good
explanations do not introduce objects not given in the experience, and thus
concludes that the usual external world propositions beat out skeptical
hypotheses on grounds of simplicity.
Moser's is the more interesting position on this point, since he holds that
best explanation models allow one to defeat the skeptic and not merely lessen
the degree to which one begs the question, as is the case with Chisholm. Yet on Moser's explanatory criteria, it is
not clear that any sort of realism emerges as the winner. The usual external-world proposition posits
entities that exist independently of consciousness, i.e., that do not depend
upon minds for their existence. This does
introduce objects that are different in kind from experiences, and thus opens
Moser's accounts to Berkeleyan objections.
Berkeley can and would argue that idealism can better satisfy Moser's
explanatory criteria than can realism's external-world, mind-independent-object
propositions, since idealism can account for the same phenomena (experiences)
by having an ontology consisting of two sorts of things (minds and their
experiences) rather that Moser's three (minds, their experiences, and external
mind-independent objects).
If this is right, then Moser is back in the same position as is Chisholm, who
appeals to realist pre-analytic intuitions, or as is Russell, who solves the
problem by claiming that belief in mind-independent matter is instinctive and
that we should stick with our instinctive beliefs unless they conflict with
other instinctive beliefs.[26] Yet neither intuitions nor appeals to
instincts are convincing sources of justification. And so we have not been able to justify the representationalist
leap. Chisholm, for example, notes in
passing that on his grounds he cannot distinguish perception from hunches in
terms of the one's providing superior grounding for external world
propositions; but he doesn't pursue the point.[27] Only animal faith can bridge the gap.[28]
Since neither deduction nor any form of induction can bridge the gap, it seems
that the only way for an external-world proposition to acquire justification is
for one to be in a position to assert a connection between the external reality
and either the experiential state or the subjective proposition. Being in the required position is not a
problem for the relation between the experiential state and the subjective
proposition: one has immediate access to each.
But in the case of the external-world proposition, some sort of direct
access to external reality would be required, and this is something that
representationalism denies that one has.
Hence, the project seems impossible, as idealists since Kant have argued
forcefully. Any sort of justification
would presuppose that the subject be able to take a third-person perspective
encompassing both the external reality and the subject's own first-person perspective. Putting the point more casually, the subject
would have to be able to take a God's-eye view of the situation or be able to
"jump outside his head."[29] This is clearly impossible.
But even if it weren't, the same representationalist problems would arise: even
from the God's-eye perspective there would have to be some means by which the
subject becomes aware of the reality, and to whatever means is posited the
following questions can be addressed: Does it give the subject the reality as
it really is? Or is the resulting
awareness a function also of the means of awareness, as in the case of the
other sensory organs? Could an evil
demon be deceiving the subject? On
representationalist grounds, one would be pressed to conclude that even the
God's-eye perspective is only a higher-order subjective and nonrelational
state, and that any connection between it and an external reality is a
contingent matter that needs to be established independently. Positing a yet higher-order God's eye view
is clearly futile, once the pattern is grasped. Thus, we have not yet generated any justification for the
external world proposition, and it is a mystery how any such justification
could be generated on representationalist premises.
This is the argument with which idealists have refuted representationalists
since Kant. In some ways Kant was more
sophisticated than many of the idealists who followed him. In place of an external material world,
which they took Kant as refuting, many later idealists felt safe in filling the
void with various replacements: God, the Will, the Will to Power, projections
of one's noumenal self, the Collective Self, the Absolute, and so on. But the argument is quite general: from
premises solely about the phenomenal nothing
follows about the noumenal, not even that there is such a thing. If the subject has access only to a nonrelational
first-person perspective, then there is no way to get the perspective needed to
justify, however minimally, the belief in one noumenal candidate over another.[30]
Twentieth century antirealists have, I think, correctly grasped the full force
of Kant's argument against representationalism and used it well to argue
against 20th century foundationalists.
It is the power of the Kantian argument that explains why the
representationalist versions of foundationalism that have been offered this
century have not been greeted with enthusiasm.
Representationalism, if consistently followed, leads to the view that
justification is solely a matter of internal networking, and that truth is
either an empty concept[31]
or one that needs to be reworked along entirely conventionalist lines. Both of these conclusions are antithetical
to foundationalism.
So in order to defend foundationalism we need to go back and address the
concerns that initially motivate representationalism. Since the representationalist claim is that both skepticism and
problems of perception necessitate a nonrelational view of consciousness from
which to initiate justification, it follows that we have two projects:
answering the skeptic, and dealing with perceptual illusions and relativity on
realist grounds. In the following two
sections I will argue that from represent- ationalism's failure
antifoundationalism does not follow, by arguing that the considerations that
have led to the adoption of representationalism in the first place — skeptical
challenges and perceptual issues — can be dealt with without resorting to
representationalism.
3.5
Defeating the skeptic quickly
The standard skeptical arguments based on hallucinations, the Cartesian dream
argument, and worries about evil demons or being a brain in a vat share a
common concern. For each variant the
claim is that everything one experiences could be unreal, i.e., that one's
entire experiential reality could be completely out of relation to any external
world. The question then asked is, How
does one know it isn't? If one is not
able to establish that it isn't, one's failure is taken as tantamount to
establishing the nonrelational view of consciousness. And from the nonrelational view follows either a general
skepticism or an attempt to construct a representationalist theory of justification.
I believe the skeptical argument is invalid.
Thus I believe that one of the traditional motivations for representationalist
theories of justification is misguided.
Let us take Descartes's evil demon as our working example in analyzing the
root skeptical argument.
1. Imagine an extremely powerful and evil demon
who systematically deceives one about every conclusion one reaches.
2. If this is in fact going on, one cannot
trust any of one's conclusions.
3. So, to trust one's conclusions, one has to
show that there is no such demon.
4. This cannot be done.
5. So, one cannot trust any of one's
conclusions.
Line 4 follows because any attempt to show there is no demon would require some
premise from which the conclusion follows that there is no demon; but any such
premise would be subject to the same conditions: showing that that premise can be accepted would first
require showing that there's no demon.
The project thus mushrooms exponentially and impossibly.[32]
Skepticism can be put on the defensive by a number of self-refutation charges;
but however valid such charges are, they do not tell us what about the
skeptical strategy is wrong. For that I
think we need to note that the tricky inference in the above evil demon
argument is from lines 2 to 3. By
investigating this inference I think that we get to the heart of the problem
with the skeptic's strategy.
What actually follows directly from line 2 is:
6. To trust one's conclusions, there has to be
no demon.
The question
then is whether line 3 follows from line 6.
Does trusting one's conclusions require showing
that there is no demon, or, more generally, showing that nothing in reality
undermines the conclusion? Skeptics
generally do make this a requirement.
Barry Stroud, for example, formulates the skeptic's principle as
follows: For any possibility incompatible with our knowing something, we must
know that the possibility does not obtain if we are to know the thing in
question.[33] But to show that nothing in reality undermines
our knowledge-candidate, we would already have to know everything in
reality. The skeptical argument thus
requires omniscience as a precondition for acquiring knowledge, and this is
obviously an impossible condition to satisfy.
The point of the skeptic's principle is that one has to rule out possibilities
that are incompatible with accepting the conclusion. But — and this is the important point — in the case of the evil
demon, we would have to have some reason to think the demon is a possibility that
needs to be ruled out. This is an issue
that skeptics rarely address explicitly.[34] Why should
one accept the claim that an evil demon is a possibility? If the demon is a possibility, then one
bears the burden of ruling it out. But
until the demon is established as a possibility, there is no need to undertake
to rule it out. The skeptic does bear
an initial burden.[35]
To establish the demon as a possibility, one line of argument often resorted to
by skeptics is as follows: If it hasn't been shown that a demon is impossible,
then it is possible that a demon exists.
And since it hasn't been so shown, it follows that it is possible that a
demon exists. This argument is widely
used. In discussion and in print the
skeptic's procedure is often as follows: Imagine an evil demon; How do you know
there isn't one?; You don't; Therefore, skepticism. With the raising of the question, the assumption is that the
failure to show that there is no demon establishes it as a possibility that
undermines all of one's knowledge-candidates.
But however widely the argument is used, it fails, for it is an argumentum ad ignorantiam. In textbook form, ad ignorantiam appears as "p
has not been shown not to be so, thus we can conclude p is so." In this
form, p is granted the highest
epistemic status merely from the lack of evidence for its denial; this is
clearly fallacious. Yet the same
fallacy can be committed when lesser degrees of epistemic status are at issue. The principle behind making ad ignorantiam a fallacy is that no degree of positive epistemic status is
achieved merely from pointing out the lack of positive epistemic status of its
denial. A teacher cannot show that a
student may have cheated on a test by noting that there is no evidence to show
that the student didn't cheat. A
prosecutor cannot show that the defendant may be guilty from the fact that
nobody has presented any reason to think her innocent. Now, to grant a proposition the status of
being a possibility is to confer positive epistemic status upon it. So it is invalid to claim that a demon is a
possibility from the fact that a demon has not been shown not to be possible.
The skeptic, accordingly, needs to establish the demon as a possibility by
finding some actual positive grounds for it.
The only grounds for this ever offered is based upon human imaginative
capacities: one can imagine a powerful evil
demon bent upon systematic deception.
The principle at work, then, is: If something is imaginable, then it is
possible.[36]
To claim that something is imaginable means that the proposed scenario contains
no known internal contradictions. A
unicorn is imaginable; a round square is not.
But from the fact that nothing to one's knowledge contradicts an
imaginary construction, it does not follow that the imaginary construction is
possible in the sense the skeptic needs.
The skeptic's claim is not merely that we can noncontradictorily
construct an evil demon scenario in our heads — the claim is that out there there may be a demon doing demonish
things.[37] This is a stronger sense of epistemic
possibility. So when the skeptic asks,
How do you know that there is no evil demon?, we can properly first demand an
answer to the question, What grounds do you the skeptic have for claiming that
out there a demon may exist? And the
skeptic cannot simply rely on the fact that a demon is imaginable, for the mere
fact that our imaginative powers enable us to construct a scenario gives us no
reason to think that reality may instantiate that scenario. For something to be a possibility in the
needed sense we have to have some actual grounds for thinking that reality
could be certain way. This would
require some input from reality. But
this is not something the skeptic can provide, on principle, for the skeptic
is committed to denying that any knowledge of reality is possible.
My conclusion is that the skeptic cannot establish the demon as a
possibility. The same analysis would
apply to brains-in-a-vat and other scenarios of the same form. Possibilities are more than imaginabilities;
they require actual evidence of some sort of connection between the imaginary
construct and the real world they are claimed to be about. In the absence of any such evidence, the
offered skeptical propositions are arbitrary posits. (The arbitrary nature of
such posits is also suggested from the fact of how easy it is to generate
them.) Completely arbitrary posits have
no positive epistemic standing. And if
a posit has no positive epistemic standing, then I think that one is under no
obligation to attempt to refute it.
From this it follows that since these considerations apply to the
general skeptical scenarios, one is not under any obligation to attempt to
refute skepticism. One can show that
its method of attack is fundamentally misguided and set it aside from the
outset.
It also follows that one can even accept the skeptic's principle — that for any
possibility incompatible with one's knowledge-candidate, one must rule out
that possibility — without falling into the problem of omniscience. This is because we now have stronger
requirements for establishing possibilities: mere imaginability is not
enough. One needs some actual evidence,
however minimal, that undermines the proposition in question. Doubts are thus always particular: they
arise in the context of investigating a particular knowledge-candidate, and
they are based upon particular concrete evidence that leads one to consider as
a possibility an incompatible proposition.
General doubt of the sort skepticism requires does not and cannot
arise. Hence no general
nonrelationalism follows; and this in turns undercuts one of the sources of the
perceived need for representationalist accounts of justification.
3.6
Illusions, relativity, and direct realism
Perceptual relativity and illusions have traditionally been the other impetus
for representationalist theories of justification. The apparent problem is that such phenomena reveal that
consciousness is not a mirror of nature: a coin can appear differently when viewed
from different angles, straight railroad tracks can appear to converge, and so
on. This leads to the
representationalist conclusion that what appears cannot be the real
object.
If the fact that consciousness is not a mirror of nature is taken as a problem,
then when representationalists come to investigate the relationship between
consciousness and reality they must be operating upon the premise that
consciousness could be directly aware of reality only if it is a mirror of
nature or some sort of diaphanous medium.
Following Kelley I will call the view of consciousness this principle
embodies the diaphanous model.
I think the diaphanous model of consciousness must be rejected. This is primarily not on the grounds that
the diaphanous model leads to representationalism's insurmountable problems
and that therefore, modus tollens, whatever
leads to representationalism must be false — though I think that that is a
powerful argument. I think the model
can and should be rejected on its own grounds.
If this can be done, then we will be in a position to approach perceptual
illusions and relativity without being tempted into representationalism.
While the diaphanous model plays a fundamental role in determining one's
approach to epistemology, it gains impetus from two other philosophical
sources. Noting these sources is
important to understanding its appeal.
The first is coming to epistemology with a prior commitment to ontological
mind/body dualism. Philosophers reach
ontological dualism for a variety of reasons, but for whatever reasons dualism
encourages perceptual representationalism, as follows. If there is a metaphysical gap between the
mental and the physical, then, since the sense organs are on the physical side,
it seems natural on dualist grounds to interpret the workings of the senses as
being completely non-conscious and merely as providing an internal
display. The nonphysical mind then
grasps this internal display somehow, but since the mind is considered to be
nonphysical, there can be no intermediary mechanism needed at this point, and
so it must be via diaphanous direct confrontation that the nonphysical mind
grasps the internal display. The
nonphysical mind next has to infer a connection between the internal display
and an external reality. That is the
familiar representationalist problem.[38] And since dualism has been the historically
dominant philosophical position on the mind/body relation, it should not be
surprising that epistemological representationalism has also been dominant.[39]
Even so, representationalism is not necessarily tied to ontological
dualism. One can have a non-ontological
compartmentalization of the mind and the senses that also encourages
representationalism. If one identifies
the conscious self solely with the mind — where concepts, propositions, and
self-consciousness exist — and sees the senses as mere conduits of information
that are attached to the conscious self, then epistemological representationalism
follows. The senses then are not part
of one's consciousness: they merely register and transmit information to one's
consciousness, which is waiting at the end of the tunnel, so to speak. In this case, as with ontological dualism,
there are then two gaps to bridge, one between the conscious self and the end
result of sensory processing, and one between the conscious self and external
reality. The former is said to be
bridged by direct confrontation — i.e., diaphanously — and the latter by means
of an inference of some sort. Again,
these are the classic ingredients of representationalism.
Kelley has hypothesized that there is an epistemological source for the
diaphanous model, arising from the fact that perception can be investigated
from two perspectives, the first-person and the third-person.[40] The former yields a phenomenological account
of perception from the standpoint of the subject, the latter a scientific
account of the processes and mechanisms of perception. Each perspective yields information not
accessible to the other. From the
first-person perspective, the subject is not aware of, for example, the array
of rods and cones being stimulated in his or her eyes during an experience of
color. From the third-person
perspective, the scientist investigating rods and cones is not aware of the
feel of the subject's experiencing. An
ideal account of perception should harmoniously integrate the two — but this is
precisely where the problems arise.
Kelley suggests that the problems arise because people first approach
perception from the first-person perspective, and only in adulthood, if ever,
take account of the third-person evidence.
But from the first-person perspective, perception seems to be a
diaphanous revealing of things as they are.
The subject is aware of no processing taking place nor of any effect of
his or her sensory organs upon the experience.
One merely opens one's eyes and confronts reality — that's common
sense. If the first-person experience
of diaphanous revelation is generalized and taken, implicitly or explicitly,
as the standard for valid perception, then the facts of perceptual relativity
and illusions will be taken as being puzzling and threatening to the validity
and directness of perception.[41]
Naive realists hope to preserve diaphaneity between subject and object, usually
by writing off illusions and other problem cases as aberrations. This seems to preserve common sense, but,
for good reasons, it has not been popular among philosophers.[42] Representationalists abandon the naive
realist's version of diaphaneity, but preserve it for the relation between
conscious subject and sense data by adopting an internal mirror of nature
model; then, in order to get justified common sense propositions about the
external world, they argue that the reflections in the mirror are pretty good
guides to what is really out there.
Idealists and antirealists point out that consciousness is hardly
diaphanous, thus disqualifying naive realism, and argue further that there is
no way to determine whether the reflections in the mirror have any worth, thus
disqualifying representationalism.
Common to all three positions, however, is the diaphanous standard. Even those who reject the diaphanous model
accept its underlying premise. Rorty,
for example, argues correctly, to my mind, that the traditional mirror of
nature view is false. But then he
argues that only if consciousness were mirror of nature could human consciousness
(or any form of consciousness, for that matter) be capable of coming to know
facts objectively. Since it is not a
mirror of nature, human consciousness is not valid. There is a package-deal offered here: Either the mirror of nature
model is true and consciousness is valid, or the mirror of nature model is
false and consciousness is invalid.
But why should we accept the premise that the mirror of nature or
diaphanous model is the only way for consciousness to grasp reality?
To focus the key problem the diaphanous model presents, let us state its
argument in summary form.
1. If perception occurs by some means (e.g., a
physical sense organ), then the means influences the outcome.
2. If the means influences the outcome, then
perception is not diaphanous.
3. If perception is not diaphanous, then the
subject cannot be directly aware of the object.
4. Therefore, if perception has to take place
by a means, the subject cannot be directly aware of the object.
The
contrapositive of 4 is the startling conclusion:
4a. If the subject can be directly aware of the object, then it must occur by no means.
Facts about illusions and relativity are all taken to support premise 1, by
showing that environmental circumstances, the nature of the organ and its
prior conditioning all have something to do with the nature of the resulting
conscious state. Premise 2 is not
controversial. Premise 3 is an
implication of the diaphanous thesis; it does the major work in generating
conclusions 4 and 4a.
Any model of consciousness that holds that direct confrontation must and can
only occur diaphanously has to run into problems on metaphysical grounds. Advocates of the model, in attempting to
maintain the cognitive link between subject and object, end up denying any
identity to consciousness.
Consciousness's grasping of its object takes place by no means; it is
simply a direction upon an object; and this is made possible, recalling
Aristotle's initial formulation,[43]
by not having any identity of its own.
Yet nothing can exist with no identity.
To be is to be something; anything that exists exists as something specific. Consciousness, accordingly, must have an
identity of its own — it cannot be a diaphanous nothing or an
as-near-to-nothing as is possible.
The question then is, What is consciousness's identity? The question has two senses. The first is completely general: What is it
for a thing to be conscious? What is
consciousness as such? The second sense
of the question is more specific: How does this particular type of consciousness
(sensory, perceptual, conceptual) work?
What are the details of its particular mechanisms and processes?
Consciousness, when spoken of generally, is spoken of as either a faculty or a
state. To speak of the faculty is to
speak of what it makes possible or accomplishes. And here it seems reasonable to speak of states of
awareness. Awareness, though, is a
relational phenomenon. To be aware is
to be aware of something.
Consciousness, accordingly, is to be defined fundamentally relationally,
as awareness of an X. What can X be? Is it, as the
necessary relatum, real or not necessarily so?
Only the former can be possible, for if consciousness is simply an
awareness of something, then there is only one thing for it to be aware of:
reality. Before awareness can occur,
there must be something to be aware of.
Both logically and chronologically, therefore, reality comes first and
consciousness second. This is realism's
axiomatic general point about the metaphysical passivity of consciousness.[44] As a corollary, it follows that awareness of
one's own existence as a conscious being cannot precede awareness of
reality. As a necessarily relational
phenomenon, prior to any contact with reality a consciousness exists only
potentially, so it has no existence or source of data independent of reality to
reflect upon. One can only grasp one's
identity as a conscious being only after one has been conscious — which
requires that one be aware of reality.[45]
The big issue is of course whether having an identity prevents consciousness
from directly knowing its object, for it is the diaphanous model that has led
representationalists and idealists to resist the above realist axioms. Here we integrate the general thesis that
consciousness is metaphysically passive with the rejection of diaphaneity as
the standard for direct awareness.
As a faculty of awareness, consciousness has to be aware of reality by a
specific means and in a specific form.
The means and form depend on the identity of the particular type of
consciousness in question. This brings
us to the second and more particular sense of our question about
consciousness's identity: How does this particular type of consciousness work?
— whether the particular type in question is sensory, perceptual, or
conceptual. Since our foundational
concerns here are with the senses and whether their workings necessitate
representationalism, let us focus upon them, first taking the third-person
perspective, to make the point.
The senses evolved as response mechanisms.
Some organisms evolved with receptors able to make them aware of their
surroundings. All receptors require
energy transfer and differentiation, and different receptors evolved tuned to
different types of energy and to different features of a given energy type. Realism's first point is that the organism's
receptors' being appropriately stimulated by its environment is its awareness of its environment. If we ask what the receptor is responding
to, the answer can only be, "Reality." That's the "what" of perception. But, obviously, organisms experience
reality in different forms, since their receptors tune them to different
features in the array of energy impinging upon them. This is to raise the question of the "how" of
sensation, which depends upon the sensory receptor in question. Each type of receptor responds to its
environment in its own way, causing the subject to be aware of reality in a
particular form.
Suppose, for example, a cube suspended by a thread in a room. If a blindfolded person were to make contact
with and manipulate the suspended cube in her hands, she would have certain
experiences. If a sighted person walked
into the room and around the cube, he too would have certain experiences. If a bat flew into the room and proceeded to
fly around the room navigating by sonar, it too would have certain experiences. In each case, the object of the experiences
is the same; each organism is responding to the same thing. But in each case, to switch to the subjects'
perspective, the "raw feels" are very different. Does it follow that since the experiences are
different, the object of the experience must be different? I don't think so. The nature of these raw feels is determined by the sensory
receptor that is stimulated in each case, and it is this that determines how — not what
— the organism experiences. In each
case the object is the same — each organism is aware of the shape of the cube
— but what varies is the form or manner in which the cube's shape is
grasped. It would be an error to
conclude that since the form is different in each case, none of the organisms
is aware of the object's shape. To be
aware an organism has to be aware by some means, which means it has to respond in some form. It can't respond
in no particular form at all; magic is not an option here.
The wrong idea is to argue that since the form the awareness takes is not
identical with the object, the awareness cannot be of the object. This is to imply that there can be no
difference between the manner of the awareness and the way in which the object
exists, which is a restatement of the impossible identity thesis. In a less extreme version it is to imply
that there can only be one right way to be aware of the object, which is a
restatement of the diaphanous model.
It is by means of this latter that the facts of perceptual relativity are taken
to necessitate representationalism.
Ayer's analysis of the stick in water's appearing bent is a classic
case. Comparing the appearance of the
stick in the water and that of the stick in air, he asks which perspective is
veridical, assuming that at most one could be.
But what could the one veridical appearance be? Berkeley raises an exactly parallel issue in
the first of his Three Dialogues about the
so-called primary quality, size. Size,
he points out, is as apparently variable as are the secondary qualities, since
apparent size varies as one moves closer to or further from an object. We can ask Ayer's question: Which one
perception of the object's size is veridical?
It could only be the one in which the actual size appears. What perspective would that be? From what distance? It is clear that asking the question on this
premise leads to the conclusion that no perspective from any distance would be correct
— not even having one's nose pressed up against it — for each is just another
perspective from some distance or other.
In pattern, then, advocates of the diaphanous model begin by noting that
awareness of the same object can take different forms. Then they ask which form is correct or
veridical, implying that only one form could be veridical. But then it seems that the only one that
could be veridical is the one in which the awareness has all and only the
features the object has in itself. But
that is to say that the awareness is identical with the object. And if the awareness is identical with the
object, then there really is only one thing — the object — which is to say that
awareness of objects doesn't exist.
Against all of this, the right idea has to be that there is only one thing for
receptors to respond to — reality. But
the form the awareness takes depends on the sort of receptor involved. Many different receptors are possible, as
biology teaches us. In some cases
different receptors tune the organism to different features of the object — for
example, touch to macroscopic texture and smell to microscopic chemical
composition. In other cases, different
receptors make organisms aware of the same feature of the object but by means
of responding to different forms of energy — for example, cats' seeing shape
and humans' feeling shape and bats' hearing shape. From the standpoint of philosophical investigations into
conscious phenomena, no one of these means of awareness is more valid than any
other; each simply is a way of becoming aware of some aspect of reality. Means of awareness are more or less
informative than others, either by being more or less discriminatory or by
being more or less wide-ranging. But
the central epistemological point is the same for all of them: each makes
possible an awareness of reality.
The idea we have rejected is that there is only one valid form of awareness —
whichever one is a diaphanous revealing of the object as it really is in
itself. Rejecting the diaphanous model
allows us to recognize that the same thing can appear differently to the same
receptor under different circumstances (e.g., viewing a coin from different
angles) or to different receptors (e.g., touching and seeing the coin's
shape).
Rejecting the diaphanous model also allows us to say that two very different
things could appear the same. Only if
we operate under the assumption that valid awareness is a diaphanous revealing
of things as they are in themselves, will we expect that things with different
identities will have to appear differently.
For example, a puddle of water and a stretch of pavement are very
different things. But it is a fact that
a stretch of pavement in the distance on a hot summer's day can look like a
puddle of water. But, according to the
diaphanous model, different things should appear differently, and since in some
cases they do not, we are said to be presented with an illusion and led to distrust
our senses. Yet there is no a priori rule that says the way the two appear
must be different. If it turns out that
the arrays of energy from each that impinge upon one's eyes are similar, then
they will appear the same. That is the
way one's eyes respond to these real phenomena; to learn that the two things
are different will simply require more information than is immediately
available.
From this brief defense of direct realism, focusing on its rejection of the
diaphanous model, it follows that representationalism is not needed in response
to perceptual illusions and relativity.
It also follows that the next important question for foundationalism is
not how one justifies ordinary object propositions on the basis of subjective
nonrelational perceptual states.
"The critical problem," to agree with Maritain, "is not
'How does one pass from percipi to esse?'"[46] That way of approaching the issue is the
representationalist model we get in most 20th century foundationalism. The question is where the abstract nature
of our propositional awareness comes from and how we can say that it preserves
the connection to reality that perception has.
Showing how the connection is preserved is the same as the project of
showing how such propositions are justified.
Since that propositional form of awareness requires concepts, the basic
question is how abstract concepts are formed on the basis of one's perceptual
awareness of reality. The question is
about the transformation of awareness of reality from a concrete perceptual
form to an abstract conceptual form.
Most foundationalists nowadays do not address the abstractness issue. Operating on representationalist premises,
they are largely concerned with getting to the external world and knowing that
or being justified in believing that one is such. The direct realist approach to the issue sets aside such questions
and moves directly to the question of abstractness.
That abstractness is derivable from particularity is also attacked by idealists
and antirealists, and forms an integral part of their attack on the possibility
of foundationalism. The attack comes
as part of the attack on the "given" and consists in arguing that
perception is inadequate as a source of justification of propositions. Sellars, for example, raises this issue
explicitly:
Now the idea that epistemic facts can be analysed without remainder — even 'in
principle' — into non-epistemic facts, whether phenomenal or behavioural, or
public or private, with no matter how lavish a sprinkling of subjunctives and
hypotheticals is, I believe, a radical mistake — a mistake of a piece with the
so-called 'naturalistic fallacy' in ethics.[47]
This is the issue of the given and its justificatory connection, mythical or
not, to propositions. This is the
subject of our next chapter.
* * *
[1]50-60; and 1986, Chapter
1).
[2] Ayer (1940, Chapter 9).
[3](see also Kemp Smith,
for example [1918, pp. xxxix-xlv]).
[4]91).
[5] Kelley (1974, pp. 18-20) makes this point.
[6] Aquinas (1952, q.1, a.9).
[7] See Michael Tye (1984) for a summary of the
difficulties for the sense data
theory and how these give impetus to
adverbial theories.
[8] For example, see Moser (1989a, p. 83, n.
25).
[9]cal conjectures.
[10] It is experience so conceived that is the
subject of many of the attacks on
the "given," which we will be investigating
in
Chapter 4.
[11] Lewis (1946, p. 180).
[12] Moser (1985b, pp. 15-16).
[13] Moser (1988a, pp. 238-239).
[14] Moser (1989a, p. 161).
[15]terization is at least
partly correct.
[16] Rorty (1979, p. 136).
[17] Williams (1977, p. 179).
[18] See Sellars (1981, pp. 11-12).
[19] Sellars (1979, pp. 169-171).
[20] For example, see Lewis (1929, p. 65) and
Moser (1988a, pp. 238-239).
[21] Skepticism's argument on this point is
discussed and rejected below, in
Section 3.5.
[22] Newman (1981, p. 336).
[23] Williams (1977, p. 179).
[24] Bonjour (1978).
[25]ist anyways.
[26] Russell (1959/1912, pp. 24-25).
[27] Chisholm (1989, pp. 67-68).
[28]Cartesian Circle.
[29]293; see also p. 178).
[30]descendants
[31]truth issue, as noted in
Chapter 1.
[32]"essentially
sound" (1975, p. 9, p. 318).
[33] Stroud (1984, p. 26).
[34]part as a corrective
against complacency in one's opinions.
[35]claims.
[36]operated on" (1969,
para. 4).
[37]to the self being
deceived (1975, p. 13).
[38]propositions about
external reality.
[39] Descartes and Locke are two obviously
important cases — both were
dualists, and both were epistemological representa tionalists.
[40] Kelley (1986, p. 37).
[41]that one accepts a
diaphanous account of perception.
[42]realism.
[43] See section 3.2, p. 118.
[44]23).
[45](1958/1917, Vol. II, pp.
15-18).
[46] Maritain (1959, p. 73).
[47] Sellars (1963, p. 131).